1
Assertion and its Constitutive Norms
Michael Rescorla
Abstract: Alston, Searle, and Williamson advocate the restrictive model of assertion, according
to which certain constitutive assertoric norms restrict which propositions one may assert. Sellars
and Brandom advocate the dialectical model of assertion, which treats assertion as constituted by
its role in the game of giving and asking for reasons. Sellars and Brandom develop a restrictive
version of the dialectical model. I explore a non-restrictive version of the dialectical model. On
such a view, constitutive assertoric norms constrain how one must react if an interlocutor
challenges one’s assertion, but they do not constrain what one should assert in the first place. I
argue that the non-restrictive dialectical perspective can accommodate various linguistic
phenomena commonly taken to support the restrictive model.
1
§1. Constitutive assertoric norms
Assertion invites normative assessment from diverse perspectives. We may condemn
Iago’s lies to Othello as immoral, simultaneously commending how effectively they promote
Iago’s goals or how courteously Iago expresses himself. In rendering these judgments, we deploy
evaluative standards rooted in morality, instrumental rationality, and propriety. The evaluative
standards exhibit no special connection to language. We could readily apply them to Iago’s non-
linguistic actions. Assertion falls under general norms lacking any peculiarly linguistic character.
2
Does assertion also fall under peculiarly linguistic norms? Norms that issue, not from
general principles of morality, rationality, or social interaction, but from special features of
linguistic intercourse? Many philosophers answer affirmatively, arguing that assertion falls under
constitutive norms. On this view, assertion is analogous to a game, in that it intrinsically involves
certain rules. Someone who exhibits no sensitivity to the rules of a game does not grasp what it is
to play the game, and someone who exhibits no sensitivity to assertion’s constitutive norms does
not grasp what it is to assert a proposition. Proponents of this view include Alston (2000),
Brandom (1994), Douven (2006), Searle (1969, 2001), Sellars (1963), and Williamson (2000).
Williamson holds that assertion falls under a constitutive norm with the structure: One
should assert p only if C(p). Williamson’s candidate for ‘C(p)’ is ‘one knows p,’ yielding
The Knowledge Norm: One should assert only propositions that one knows.
Countless other norms with the same structure are possible, including:
The Honesty Norm: One should assert only propositions that one believes.
The Truth Norm: One should assert only true propositions.
The Warrant Norm: One should assert only propositions that one believes
with ‘sufficient’ warrant.
I will call such norms restrictive, since they restrict which propositions one may assert. The
restrictive model of assertion holds that assertion falls under constitutive restrictive norms.
Alston, Brandom, Searle, and Sellars endorse the restrictive model, as do most philosophers who
embrace constitutive assertoric norms.
One can also imagine non-restrictive assertoric norms. I focus on norms with the
structure: If one asserts p, then, if D(p), one must φ(p). Theories based entirely upon norms with
this structure reject any notion of ‘assertibility’ or ‘appropriate assertion.’ They characterize
3
assertion solely in terms of how it alters the speaker’s normative standing, not in terms of which
assertions are permissible.
The most promising candidates for non-restrictive assertoric norms reflect what I will call
the dialectical model of assertion, which regards assertion as essentially a move within ‘the
game of giving and asking for reasons.’ The intuitive idea here is that, by asserting a proposition,
I commit myself to defending the proposition when faced with challenges and counter-
arguments. I can cancel the dialectical commitment by retracting my assertion, but until then the
commitment stands. Although the basic idea is ancient, recent discussion of it derives mainly
from the writings of Hamblin (1971), Sellars (1963), and Toulmin (1958). However we elaborate
this idea, the resulting account will likely feature non-restrictive norms that describe how to react
if another speaker contests an asserted proposition.
One can develop the dialectical model in either a restrictive or non-restrictive direction.
On the restrictive version, constitutive assertoric norms codify how to answer challenges and
counter-arguments, and they also constrain which propositions one can initially assert. Brandom
(1994), Sellars (1963), and Watson (2004) advocate views along these lines. I will explore a non-
restrictive version of the dialectical model. On this view, constitutive assertoric norms constrain
how I must react if someone challenges my assertion, but they do not constrain what I should
assert in the first place. Morality, propriety, or rationality might require that I assert only
propositions with some desired feature. No constitutive norm of assertion imposes any such
requirement. For instance, a lie violates no constitutive assertoric norm, although the liar incurs
dialectical commitments that she may or may not be able to discharge.
A non-restrictive version of the dialectical model may appear somewhat implausible. I
am aware of only a single recent commentator, MacFarlane (2003, 2005), who advocates
4
anything resembling it. I will urge that some popular arguments for the restrictive model are
seriously flawed. I will furthermore argue that the non-restrictive dialectical perspective can
accommodate various linguistic phenomena commonly taken to support the restrictive model.
§2. Norms and practices
In this section, I develop a rough conception of how constitutive assertoric norms differ
from non-constitutive assertoric norms. I hope that the conception will be fairly uncontroversial.
Advocates of constitutive assertoric norms typically emphasize the analogy with games,
as in the following passage by Williamson: “one might suppose… that someone who knowingly
asserts a falsehood has thereby broken a rule of assertion, much as if he had broken a rule of a
game; he has cheated. On this view, the speech act, like a game and unlike the act of jumping, is
constituted by rules” (p. 238). The analogy with games seems helpful, so we should explore it in
detail. How exactly is assertion more analogous to a game than to an activity such as jumping?
The contrast between playing a game and jumping illustrates a more general contrast
between what I will call practices and mere activities. Besides games, sample practices include:
dances, like the waltz or the tango; religious ceremonies, like weddings; fraternity initiation rites;
performing Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony. Every practice is associated with “internal” standards
of normative assessment codified by norms dictating how to execute the practice correctly. The
norms for performing Beethoven’s Fifth Symphony demand that musicians play the notes of
Beethoven’s score at roughly the indicated tempo. The norms for dancing the waltz demand that
dancers move in time with the music, selecting their movements from a fixed repertoire of dance
steps. Agents who violate a practice’s norms do not implement the practice correctly, but they
5
may still implement the practice. A devious gambler might repeatedly cheat during a poker
game. He plays poker incorrectly, but he plays poker nonetheless.
The connection with internal evaluative standards differentiates practices from mere
activities, like jumping, bathing, or holding hands. A mere activity falls under general norms,
like those of morality, propriety, and rationality, but it does not fall under specialized norms that
govern correct execution of the activity. There is no correct or incorrect way to bathe. There is
no correct or incorrect way to hold hands.
The contrast between practices and mere activities suggests the following formulation: a
norm is constitutive of a practice iff one must obey the norm to engage correctly in the practice.
In some weak sense, any activity involves constitutive requirements: requirements one
must satisfy to count as engaging in the activity. One must immerse parts of one’s body in some
liquid to count as ‘bathing.’ Two people must achieve physical contact between their hands to
count as ‘holding hands.’ But only practices enshrine constitutive standards that govern correct
execution of the activity. Any practice engenders a three-fold division between actions that do
not count as engaging in the practice, actions that count as engaging in it correctly, and actions
that count as engaging in it incorrectly. A mere activity engenders only a two-fold division
between actions that count as engaging in the activity and actions that do not. We might describe
this contrast by saying that all activities involve constitutive requirements, which one must
satisfy to engage in the activity, while practices also involve constitutive norms, which one must
satisfy to engage in the practice correctly.
There are basically two ways one might analyze constitutive assertoric norms within the
framework developed thus far. Most straightforwardly, we might treat assertion as a self-
contained practice governed by constitutive norms. On this view, constitutive assertoric norms
6
describe how to engage correctly in the practice of assertion, where that practice can be
characterized in isolation from other speech acts. Alston, Searle, and Williamson adopt this
approach. A somewhat less straightforward approach treats assertion as a move within a larger
practice, much as a home run is a move within the larger practice of baseball. On this view,
constitutive assertoric norms describe how to engage correctly in some segment of the larger
practice. Sellars and Brandom adopt this approach, insisting that assertion is individuated by its
role within the game of giving and asking for reasons, which I will often refer to as ‘reasoned
discourse.’ If Sellars and Brandom are correct, then assertion can be fully characterized only
through its normative relations to other speech acts, such as questioning and challenging.
Although I will side with Sellars and Brandom in this dispute, our terminology should not
take sides. I offer the following characterization. A norm is a norm of assertion iff my assertoric
performances are relevant to whether I violate it. A norm is constitutive of assertion iff it is a
norm of assertion and it is constitutive of a practice to which assertion is intrinsically connected.
This formulation is rough, but it is general enough to encompass Alston, Searle, and Williamson
(since the practice might simply be assertion itself) and Sellars and Brandom (since the practice
might be the game of giving and asking for reasons). Our formulation reflects the intuitive idea
that assertion has an intrinsically normative dimension. We can characterize assertion’s
fundamental nature only by delineating specialized norms that govern its correct execution. I
think this conception guides many philosophers, either more or less explicitly.
On the other hand, many philosophers repudiate specialized assertoric norms. Davidson
is a particularly emphatic opponent (1984, pp. 265-280). In my terminology, Davidson regards
conversation as a mere activity, rather than as a practice incorporating its own internal standards
of normative assessment. For Davidson, there is no significant distinction between ‘correctly’ or
7
‘incorrectly’ executing speech acts. One either executes them or one does not. Such an approach
precludes anything like constitutive norms of speech acts. It countenances only whatever
normativity results from subsuming conversation under extra-linguistic norms. On Davidson’s
approach, assertion is not intrinsically normative, although, like any action, it falls under norms
of morality, propriety, rationality, etc.
My discussion highlights the elementary but crucial distinction between a norm’s content
and its normative status. When discussing ‘norms of assertion,’ it is never enough merely to
specify a norm’s content, i.e. what the norm demands. One must also specify what normative
force it exerts. In some sense, it is clearly a ‘norm of assertion’ that one ‘should’ speak honestly.
The question is whether the Honesty Norm enjoys a specifically linguistic grounding beyond
what it receives from morality, legality, propriety, rationality, and other extra-linguistic factors.
Is the Honesty Norm constitutive of assertion? Or does it merely result from subsuming assertion
under more general normative patterns?
§3. The dialectical model of assertion
According to the dialectical model, assertion involves a commitment to defend the
asserted proposition if challenged. The model develops this idea, in part, by positing constitutive
norms that regulate how one should respond when other speakers challenge one’s assertions.
Does ‘defending’ my assertion require arguments that actually support my position, or
that I regard as doing so, that my interlocutor regards as doing so, or something else? Can my
argument employ any non-question-begging premises, or only true premises, or only premises
my interlocutor accepts, or something else? How we answer such questions determines which
norms we embrace. For instance, selecting the first answer to each question suggests
8
The Defense Norm: When challenged to defend an asserted proposition, one must
either provide a cogent, non-circular argument for the proposition or else retract it,
where a ‘cogent’ argument is one whose premises provide rational support for its conclusion.
Often, proponents of the dialectical model regard the Defense Norm as too strong, preferring
instead something closer to
The Default-Challenge Norm: When faced with a legitimate challenge to defend an
asserted proposition, one must either provide a cogent, non-circular argument for the
proposition or else retract it.
For example, a challenge to the assertion “I have hands” might count as legitimate only if the
challenger sketches a compelling skeptical scenario in which I do not have hands. Leite (2005)
presents a theory of reasoned discourse based on something like the Default-Challenge Norm. He
does not endorse the further claim that this norm is constitutive of assertion. Brandom endorses
the further claim. In (Rescorla, 2009b), I defend a weakened variant of the Defense Norm against
Leite and Brandom. We may ignore these internecine skirmishes here.
The dialectical model also describes how one should respond to counter-arguments
against an asserted proposition. Again, many variations are possible. Most accounts feature
something like the following norm:
The Retraction Norm: When faced with a counter-argument against an asserted
proposition, one must rebut the counter-argument or else retract the proposition.
Note that we can accept the Retraction Norm even if we reject anything resembling the Defense
or Default-Challenge Norm, a combination of views suggested by (MacFarlane, 2005, p. 334).
If I seek to discharge a dialectical commitment, as opposed to canceling it, then I must
provide an argument. How do I provide an argument? By asserting additional propositions as the
9
argument’s premises. Thus, assertion plays a dual role in reasoned discourse: through it, one both
undertakes and discharges dialectical commitments. As Brandom puts it:
[A]ssertings… are in the fundamental case what reasons are asked for, and what giving a
reason always consists in. The kind of commitment that a claim of the assertional sort is
an expression of is something that can stand in need of (and so be liable to the demand
for) a reason; and it is something that can be offered as a reason (1994, p. 167).
Assertion’s dual role might appear to generate a vicious regress, since discharging dialectical
commitments embroils one in further commitments. Proponents of the dialectical model evince
various reactions to this regress. Brandom tries to halt the regress through the Default-Challenge
Norm, which allows us to say that certain assertions require defense only given special effort by
one’s interlocutor. In contrast, (Rescorla, 2009a) argues that the regress is not worrisome: either
speaker and interlocutor agree upon mutually acceptable relevant premises, in which case the
regress halts, or speaker and interlocutor do not agree upon mutually acceptable premises, in
which case the speaker leaves certain dialectical commitments undischarged.
2
Again, we may
ignore these complications here.
To undercut the dialectical model, some critics emphasize that serious dialectical
interaction is a relatively rare phenomenon. We often assert propositions without engaging one
another in reasoned discourse. Yet this undeniable fact is consistent with the dialectical model,
which holds that asserting a proposition is performing an action that occupies a certain normative
role within reasoned discourse. Such a view can allow that assertion sometimes occurs outside
reasoned discourse. Non-dialectical assertoric performances may even statistically outnumber
performances within reasoned discourse. The model claims only that non-dialectical assertoric
performances are explanatorily derivative from core performances within reasoned discourse.
10
Part of what makes a given linguistic performance an assertion, as opposed to some other speech
act, are the dialectical commitments the speaker assumes, commitments that become operative
once the speaker engages fellow conversationalists in reasoned discourse. In this sense, assertion
is ‘intrinsically connected’ to reasoned discourse.
Not all assertions are moves within reasoned discourse, but all assertions are potential
moves within reasoned discourse. Whenever I assert some proposition, other speakers may
challenge me to defend it or even provide counter-arguments against it. And then I face a choice.
I can extrude myself from reasoned discourse (“I’m not going to argue with you”). I can engage
in reasoned discourse incorrectly, trying to defend my assertion but doing so inadequately. Or I
can engage in reasoned discourse correctly, vindicating my assertion or else retracting it. Thus,
the norms of reasoned discourse describe a normative infrastructure that lurks beneath the
surface of quotidian conversation, perpetually threatening to emerge. According to the dialectical
model, assertion is individuated by its place within this normative infrastructure and hence is
possible only against the background provided by it.
But aren’t there are many assertoric performances through which I undertake no
dialectical commitment whatsoever? Suppose I engage someone in casual small-talk at a cocktail
party. I might assert a proposition to initiate a new topic or promote a diverting conversation.
Yet, one might urge, it hardly seems appropriate to greet such an assertion with challenges or
counter-arguments. So the dialectical model must be fundamentally mistaken in tying assertoric
force so closely to dialectical commitment.
In response, note that there are many elliptical gambits through which I can introduce a
new topic or promote an entertaining conversation. Instead of asserting p, I might say, “I’m
curious what you think about p.” I thereby put forward a proposition p without undertaking any
11
dialectical commitment. If my interlocutor responds by arguing against p, I might simply reply,
“Very interesting points.” It would be outrageous for my interlocutor to then demand, “Well,
aren’t you going to respond to my arguments? Or, at least, retract what you said?”. That demand
seems far more legitimate if I initially asserted p. Although the demand may be obnoxious or
uncouth, there is a clear sense in which it is invited by an assertion that p but not by more
elliptical ways of putting forward p. This contrast suggests the following analysis: assertion
always involves some element of dialectical commitment, but general norms of social propriety
may render it more or less appropriate to press the speaker to discharge those commitments.
Most proponents of the dialectical model combine it with the restrictive model. Brandom
treats the Warrant and Default-Challenge Norms as constitutive of assertion. Watson (2004)
develops a similar account, supplemented with a restrictive norm along these lines:
The Defensibility Norm: One should assert only propositions one can defend with
cogent, non-circular arguments.
We can imagine numerous variants, such as:
The Known Defensibility Norm: One should not assert propositions one knows
one cannot defend with cogent, non-circular arguments.
In what follows, I will investigate the prospects for a non-restrictive version of the dialectical
model. I will examine various popular arguments for the restrictive model, urging that any
uncontroversial phenomena adduced by them can be accommodated just as well by the non-
restrictive dialectical perspective. For additional development of the non-restrictive dialectical
perspective, see (Rescorla, 2007).
§4. Does the dialectical model entail the restrictive model?
12
One might suspect that the dialectical model collapses into the restrictive model, and
hence that the non-restrictive dialectical perspective is incoherent. If assertion involves a
commitment to defend what one says, then shouldn’t one avoid asserting propositions one cannot
defend, or at least propositions one knows one cannot defend? More explicitly, one might reason:
(A) (i) By asserting a proposition, one commits oneself to defending it.
(ii) One should not undertake commitments one knows one cannot discharge.
(iii) Hence, one should not assert propositions one knows one cannot defend.
Argument (A) purports to derive a restrictive norm from the basic intuition (i) underlying the
dialectical model. If ‘defend’ means ‘defend with cogent, non-circular arguments,’ then the
derived norm is the Known Defensibility Norm.
In evaluating (A), a central consideration is the normative force of the ‘should’ in (ii) and
(iii). Undoubtedly, one should not undertake commitments one knows one cannot keep, if one
wants to keep one’s commitments. But this establishes only that
If one wants to keep one’s commitments, one should not assert propositions one knows
one cannot defend,
which is a hypothetical norm about how to achieve a certain goal (keeping one’s commitments),
not a constitutive norm of assertion. One might instead construe (ii) as a moral norm. Under this
construal, (A) is valid only if ‘should’ in (iii) likewise expresses moral obligation, in which case
(iii) is moral norm rather than a norm describing how to execute assertion correctly.
Another idea would be to treat (ii) as somehow constitutive of commitment in general, in
which case it seems more plausible that (i) and (ii) jointly yield a constitutive norm of assertion.
But, as I will now argue, this suggestion also faces problems.
13
Consider Rawls on promising. Rawls holds that promising falls under a constitutive norm
that “reads roughly as follows: if one says the words ‘I promise to do X’ in the appropriate
circumstances, one is to do X, unless certain excusing conditions obtain” (1971, p. 345). Rawls
explains our obligation to keep promises as resulting from interaction between this norm and the
Principle of Fairness, a general moral prohibition against free-riding on just practices. He does
not mention a constitutive norm against promising to φ when one has no intention of φ-ing or
even when one knows one cannot φ. A natural interpretation, then, is that Rawls does not think
insincere promises violate any constitutive norm of promising. Violation occurs when one fails
to keep the promise, but not necessarily before. By promising to φ when I have no intention of φ-
ing, I may be morally culpable. But moral transgressions are not necessarily violations of
constitutive promissory norms. For instance, suppose I promise to φ while feeling quite certain I
will not be able to φ; shortly after the promise, it becomes both possible and advantageous for
me to φ, so I φ. On the proposed view, I need violate no constitutive norm of promising,
although I undoubtedly violate a moral norm.
Alston (2000) and Searle (1969) argue that promising falls under a restrictive constitutive
norm that one promise to φ only if one intends to φ. Other philosophers, such as Thomson (1990,
p. 303), question whether promising involves constitutive norms at all. I take no stand regarding
which account is correct. My point is just that there is nothing incoherent about the conception I
have attributed to Rawls. One can imagine a practice along these lines, even if that practice is not
ours, and even if there are good reasons for preferring our own. The proposed practice provides a
coherent model of commitment as regulated by norms requiring one to fulfill one’s commitments
but no norms restricting which commitments one undertakes. It thereby casts doubt upon the
14
thesis that (ii) is constitutive of commitment in general, and hence upon (A)’s attempt to derive a
constitutive restrictive norm from the dialectical model.
There is something defective about performing action within practice P if I know doing
so will eventually force me to engage in P incorrectly. But that does not entail that itself,
rather than some action subsequent to , violates P’s constitutive norms. The following principle
is plausible: engaging in a practice constitutively requires at least pretending that one seeks to
engage in it correctly. Thus, depending on the details of the case, my -ing is defective in one of
two ways. Either I do not really seek to engage in P correctly, in which case my behavior is
disingenuous, since I misleadingly pretend that I seek to engage in P correctly. Or else I seek to
engage in P correctly, in which case it is pragmatically incoherent to , since I know doing so
will eventually force me to violate P’s constitutive norms. In neither case need we posit an
additional constitutive norm, a norm violated by , beyond those constitutive norms will
eventually induce me to violate.
The non-restrictive dialectical perspective may not yet seem plausible. But it does seem
coherent. In particular, constitutive features of commitment do not induce a collapse of the
dialectical model into the restrictive model.
§5. Representing oneself as believing/knowing that p
I can speak insincerely. It may even be common knowledge between myself and my
interlocutor that I am speaking insincerely (Rumfitt, 1995). But I cannot assert a proposition
while abandoning all pretensions towards speaking sincerely. If I say “Frank is an excellent
student” while blatantly smirking and winking, then I do not assert that Frank is an excellent
student, except perhaps in some attenuated sense that does not interest us here. My body
15
language subverts the display of candor that is a necessary concomitant to genuinely, non-
ironically asserting a proposition. Assertion essentially involves at least a pretense of sincerity.
It is tempting to suppose that the essential link between assertion and apparent sincerity
supports the restrictive model. If assertion essentially involves a display of sincerity, then surely
one should assert a proposition only when the display is genuine.
This reasoning is fallacious. It slides without any argument from uncontroversial claims
about assertion’s constitutive requirements to highly controversial claims about assertion’s
constitutive norms. A constitutive requirement of assertion is that one adopt a show of
conviction, just as a constitutive requirement of bathing is that one immerse part of one’s body in
liquid. In neither case does it follow that the activity involves constitutive norms: norms
specifying how to execute the activity correctly. Someone who abandons the pretense of
sincerity does not engage incorrectly in assertion. She does not assert a proposition at all. Of
course, given that assertion involves a display of sincerity, and given the moral principle that one
should avoid deceiving others, it follows that one should speak sincerely. But that still does not
show that any norm is constitutive of assertion. It only illustrates that assertion falls under
general norms that apply to many other actions.
Few philosophers would embrace the fallacious reasoning in the simplistic form just
criticized. But similar mistakes plague much more sophisticated expositions.
Unger (1975, p. 253) advocates the following thesis: “If someone asserts, states, or
declares that something is so, then it follows that he represents himself as knowing that it is so.”
Let us call this Unger’s Thesis. According to DeRose (2002, p. 180), Unger’s Thesis entails that
the Knowledge Norm is constitutive of assertion: “For our purposes, these are just two sides of
16
the same coin: If one represents oneself as knowing that p by asserting p, then, to avoid falsely
representing oneself, one should follow the rule of asserting only what one knows.”
I am not convinced that Unger’s Thesis is true. But the key point here is that Unger’s
Thesis does not entail that the Knowledge Norm is constitutive of assertion. At best, Unger’s
Thesis identifies a constitutive requirement of assertion: to assert p, one must represent oneself
as knowing p. That assertion embodies this constitutive requirement does not entail that there are
correct or incorrect ways of asserting a proposition. Only a confusion between constitutive
requirements and constitutive norms, or between constitutive and non-constitutive norms, could
make the inference from Unger’s thesis to the restrictive model seem obvious and unproblematic.
Davidson, who endorses a weakened version of Unger’s Thesis that replaces knowledge with
belief, puts the point succinctly: “What we do in making an assertion is represent ourselves as
believing what we say, and so we may be morally at fault if it turns out that we don’t believe
what we asserted. But moral error is not linguistic error” (2005, p. 123).
Hence, there is no deductive entailment from Unger’s Thesis, or similar doctrines, to the
restrictive model of assertion. But one might urge that some kind of abductive entailment holds.
In the previous section, we mentioned the following extremely plausible principle: engaging in a
practice constitutively requires at least pretending that one seeks to engage in it correctly. This
principle, combined with the Honesty Norm, entails that assertion constitutively requires at least
a pretense of sincerity. Similar derivations are possible for Unger’s Thesis, or for the weakened
version of it espoused by Davidson (Williamson, 2000, p. 252). So the restrictive model can
explain assertion’s constitutive requirements.
One problem with the proposed abductive argument is that one might simply deny that
assertion’s constitutive requirements need explaining. Davidson urges that his weakened version
17
of Unger’s Thesis follows directly from the conceptual analysis of assertion (1984, p. 270). It is
not clear that the proposed abductive argument exerts any force against Davidson’s position.
However, the abductive argument poses a challenge to the non-restrictive dialectical
perspective. The argument shows that the restrictive model easily accommodates relatively
uncontroversial features of assertion. It is not clear that a non-restrictive dialectical account can
explain those same features. Apparently, I can undertake a commitment to defend some
proposition without any pretense of believing it. For instance, I might promise a friend that I will
defend some proposition against all challenges and counter-arguments, even while emphasizing
that I do not believe the proposition. How, then, can the non-restrictive dialectical perspective
explain why assertion requires apparent sincerity?
In §3, I noted that assertion occupies a dual role in reasoned discourse: through it, one
both undertakes and discharges dialectical commitments. So far, I have emphasized the first of
these two roles. As I will now argue, focusing on the second role helps defuse the present
objection to non-restrictive dialectical theories. Schematically: while apparent sincerity may not
be necessary for undertaking dialectical commitment, it is necessary for discharging dialectical
commitments; so assertion’s role in discharging dialectical commitment generates a constitutive
requirement of apparent sincerity.
I begin by exploring more closely the nature of “dialectical commitment.” In developing
the dialectical model, we should not depict reasoned discourse as a rhetorical exercise utterly
detached from the participants’ beliefs. By asserting a proposition, I make it my position, not
merely a position I agree to defend for the sake of argument. Assertoric commitment is not just a
commitment to providing arguments or to rebutting counter-arguments. As I will put it, assertion
involves a commitment to advocate for one’s position, i.e. to present it as worthy of belief.
18
Advocacy is not included in what the Defense and Default-Challenge Norms demand.
Specifically, it requires me to present my arguments as providing compelling reasons for
believing the asserted proposition. For instance, it is not enough merely to say, “Here are some
arguments that p, but I don’t myself find them plausible.” If I issue this disclaimer, I cease to
advocate for the asserted proposition. (A lawyer might tell the jury, “Here are some arguments
for my client’s innocence. I don’t find them convincing, but you should make up your own
mind.” The lawyer does not advocate for her client, no matter how impressive her arguments.)
How should we capture ‘advocacy’ through precise norms? I employ a fairly minimalist
formulation: advocacy involves presenting the premises of one’s argument as providing reason
for believing the asserted proposition. So construed, I think that advocacy underlies several
familiar versions of the dialectical model, including (Brandom, 1994). It is compatible with
various dialectical norms. For instance, we could supplement the Defense Norm with the proviso
that, when providing cogent arguments, one must advocate for one’s position. We could add an
analogous proviso to a norm demanding arguments that one’s interlocutor finds cogent, or that
the speaker finds cogent.
According to the dialectical model, assertion is individuated by its role in reasoned
discourse. Part of this role consists in the fact that speakers discharge dialectical commitments by
asserting propositions. So assertion, by its very nature, is a means for discharging dialectical
commitments. Clearly, I need not intend each assertoric performance as contributing to the
discharge of a dialectical commitment. I might assert p on a whim, without envisaging a broader
argumentative goal. Nevertheless, there is a clear sense in which even this whimsical assertion
contributes to the future putative discharge of dialectical commitments. Metaphorically: the
assertion requires no supplementation for me to cite p as a premise in future arguments. I need
19
merely re-affirm my prior assertion. This element of redundancy differentiates assertion from
speech acts like conjecturing p or putting p forward. If I conjecture p or put it forward, then I
cannot subsequently present it as affording reason for belief without fundamentally transforming
my standing towards it. If I assert p, no such transformation is required. By asserting p, I have
already presented it a potential premise in future arguments I may or may not offer.
As Brandom puts it, then, “[u]ttering a sentence with assertional force or significance is
putting it forward as a potential reason… Assertions are essentially fit to be reasons” (1994, p.
168). Part of what makes my speech act an assertion of p, rather than a conjecture or a mere
putting forward of p, is that I present p as providing reason for believing other propositions.
There may not be any specific proposition that I advance p as affording reason for believing. But
I present it as a reason to be invoked, when relevant, in future advocacy.
We may now offer the following argument that assertion constitutively requires a
pretense of sincerity:
(B) (i) By asserting a proposition, one presents it as providing reason for believing other
propositions.
(ii) One presents a proposition as providing reason for believing other propositions only
if one maintains some minimal pretense of believing it.
(iii) Hence, one asserts a proposition only if one maintains some minimal pretense of
believing it.
(i) and (ii) entail the desired conclusion (iii). The previous four paragraphs argued that (i) seems
plausible once we accept a suitable version of the dialectical model. (ii) seems plausible
whatever our conception of assertion. Suppose I utter p while indicating, perhaps through winks
or other body language, that I do not believe p. Then how can I present p as providing reason for
20
believing any other proposition q? I can advance it as a reason why some other person (including
my interlocutor) might believe q, but not as a reason why one should believe q. Lacking a
minimal show of credence in p, I cannot depict it as having any reason-giving force.
Revisiting an earlier example, suppose I promise a friend that I will vigorously defend p,
even while emphasizing to my friend that I do not believe p. Although I thereby undertake a kind
of dialectical commitment, I do not present p as affording reason for believing any other
proposition. Thus, my speech act does not contribute to the future putative discharge of
dialectical commitments. So it is not an assertion.
In motivating (i), we invoked structural features of reasoned discourse that any plausible
version of the non-restrictive dialectical perspective should accept. Moreover, (i) articulates a
constitutive requirement, not a constitutive norm, so there is no obvious entailment from (i) to
claims about assertion’s constitutive norms. Hence, (B) neither presupposes nor entails that
assertion falls under constitutive restrictive norms. In this way, our argument shows how a non-
restrictive dialectical account can explain why assertion requires apparent sincerity.
To buttress (B), imagine a dialectical practice that is “devil’s advocate all the way down.”
In this hypothetical practice, I can advance a proposition p, thereby incurring a commitment to
defend it. I defend p by advancing additional propositions as premises in an argument for p. My
interlocutor may in turn challenge those premises. However, neither my initial utterance of p nor
my subsequent defense of it need involve any pretense of sincerity. I merely advance and defend
propositions for the sake of argument, as when participants in our own dialectical practice
employ the following locutions: “Well, I’m not saying that I believe this myself, but some would
argue as follows,” “Proponents of p would respond to your counter-argument by saying q,” etc.
21
Could the hypothetical practice exist autonomously from normal assertoric practice? For
instance, must not participants in any stable, coherent dialectical practice have available a speech
act through which they at least pretend to believe claims about word-meanings or justificatory
relations between propositions? Leaving such questions aside, it seems clear that the hypothetical
practice differs dramatically from our own dialectical activity. The key difference is that, even if
participants in the hypothetical practice offer cogent arguments, they do not advance those
arguments as providing reasons for belief. In this sense, the practice hardly counts as a “game of
giving and asking for reasons.” Participants in the practice may provide arguments, but they do
not advocate for propositions. They undertake a fundamentally different kind of dialectical
commitment than that which we undertake through assertion. Apparently, then, any dialectical
practice remotely like ours requires a speech act through which one undertakes dialectical
commitments and throughout the performance of which one maintains some pretense of belief.
It is likely that reasoning similar to (B) can explain Davidson’s weakened version of
Unger’s Thesis, according to which someone who asserts p represents herself as believing p.
Specifically, we might replace (ii) with the following premise: one can present a proposition as
providing reason for believing other propositions only if one represents oneself as believing it.
What about the original version of Unger’s Thesis, based upon knowledge rather than belief? We
might invoke the much stronger premise (ii'): one can present a proposition as providing reason
for believing other propositions only if one represents oneself as knowing it. Although I do not
myself find (ii') particularly congenial, it strikes me as no less plausible than Unger’s Thesis.
Unger himself (1975, pp. 206-214) advocates a position somewhat reminiscent of (ii'): if X’s
reason for believing something is that p, then X knows that p. Williamson (2000, pp. 184-208)
advances a kindred doctrine: only known propositions are evidence for other propositions. Thus,
22
while the topic obviously requires further discussion, it hardly seems clear that Unger’s Thesis
poses insuperable difficulties for the non-restrictive dialectical perspective.
3
§6. Committing oneself to the truth of what one asserts
Peirce remarks that assertion involves an essentially normative ingredient: “This
ingredient, the assuming of responsibility, which is so prominent in solemn assertion, must be
present in every genuine assertion” (1934, p. 386). One can formulate Peirce’s insight in various
ways: a speaker commits himself to the proposition asserted; he takes responsibility for its truth;
he endorses the proposition; he stakes himself to the truth of the proposition; and so forth.
Many philosophers suggest that these Peircean formulations support the restrictive
model. For instance, Searle urges that “asserting commits the speaker to the truth of the
proposition asserted” (2001, p. 147). He infers that the Truth Norm is constitutive of assertion.
As he puts it, “[s]uch principles as ‘you ought to tell the truth,’ ‘you ought not to lie,’ or ‘you
ought to be consistent in your assertion’ are internal to the notion of assertion. You do not need
any external moral principle to have the relevant commitments. The commitment to truth is built
into the structure of the intentionality of the assertion” (2001, 181).
An obvious objection to Searle’s argument is that it rests upon the somewhat obscure
notion ‘committing oneself to the truth of a proposition.’ As MacFarlane (2005, p. 334) notes
while developing this objection, the most straightforward notion of commitment is commitment
to do something. I commit myself to attending a conference, to paying my Visa bill, and so on.
But an assertion that p is not, in general, a commitment to make it the case that p. In what sense,
then, do I ‘commit’ myself to the truth of a proposition that I assert?
23
One might propose that the relevant commitment is to believing the proposition, or
perhaps to judging that it is true. But what is it to undertake such a commitment? I can promise
to accumulate evidence and to survey it judiciously, but I can hardly promise what conclusions I
will draw. I can commit myself to self-inducing the belief that p, perhaps by swallowing a pill
with appropriate belief-altering properties. Obviously, this commitment is not an element of
normal assertion. On the other hand, if the putative commitment is to its already being the case
that I believe or judge p, then this revives the question of how to understand a commitment that
is not commitment to some course of action.
Another proposal is that, as Searle puts it, “[i]n making an assertion we take
responsibility for truth, sincerity, and evidence… These responsibilities are met only if the world
is such that the utterance is true, the speaker is sincere, and the speaker has evidence for the
assertion” (2001, p. 176). The relevant notion of “taking responsibility” is still fairly obscure. I
can take responsibility for doing something, such as watering my neighbor’s plants while he
vacations. I can take responsibility for having caused some proposition to be true. But what is it
to take responsibility for a proposition being true when I played no role in its truth? I can take
responsibility for compensating my interlocutor if what I assert turns out not to true. Yet this
obviously has no bearing upon typical assertoric performances. Another idea, explored by Alston
(2000, p. 54-63), is to construe ‘x takes responsibility for its being the case that p’ in terms of the
censure, blame, or reproach that x would or should encounter if it turns out that x did not believe
p. I will discuss these negative reactive attitudes in §7. Alston eventually rejects construals based
upon reactive attitudes, adopting instead the following analysis: “x takes responsibility for its
being the case that p in uttering s iff, in uttering s, x subjects his utterance to a rule that implies it
is permissible for x to utter s only if p (p. 60). He argues that this rule-based analysis is more
24
explanatorily fundamental than one based upon negative reactive attitudes, since it explains the
source of those attitudes and also their pattern of distribution across various cases. However, the
rule-based analysis embodies something quite close to the restrictive model. Thus, as Alston
would doubtless acknowledge, it cannot subserve an argument for the restrictive model.
In ordinary conversation, we frequently adduce a speaker’s ‘conversational
commitments.’ We say that a speaker is committed to some proposition, or to some proposition
being true. We criticize a speaker who cannot defend his conversational commitments when
faced with challenges or counter-arguments. Thus, I think that Searle evokes fundamental
intuitions about assertion. But the non-restrictive dialectical perspective arguably accommodates
these Peircean intuitions just as well as the restrictive model. We can gloss ‘commitment to the
truth of a proposition’ as ‘commitment to defending (or advocating for) the truth of a
proposition.’ On this construal, a speaker who is ‘committed to a proposition’ or ‘committed to
the truth of a proposition’ is committed to defending the proposition within reasoned discourse.
Crucially, a commitment to defending the truth of what one says is not the same as a
commitment to speaking the truth in the first place.
It might seem that the proposed dialectical analysis provide a natural entrée for the
restrictive model. Commitment to defending the truth of what one says may not be literally the
same as commitment to speaking the truth. The former commitment may not even entail the
latter. But they seem to go together as a natural package. Why would I incur the former
commitment if I don’t also incur the latter?
The adversarial legal system provides an instructive, albeit imperfect, analogy. As
instantiated within the United States, this practice is governed by a complex set of constitutive
norms, some codified and others implicit in the common law tradition. Two lawyers advocate for
25
competing sides, with the verdict decided by a neutral third party. The lawyers are committed to
defending their positions as effectively as possible. Blatant failure to do so constitutes
malpractice and merits sanction. Yet Applbaum (2000) argues that advocacy within this system
falls under no global Honesty Norm. As Applbaum puts it, “over the course of representing a
client, a lawyer forms reasonable beliefs… about the various factual propositions at issue in the
trial, and… zealous advocacy often requires her to attempt to persuade the jury to believe the
opposite” (p. 106). The relevant ‘reasonable beliefs’ sometimes rise to the level of knowledge.
Legal norms do not allow lawyers to say just anything. Complex rules of evidence forbid certain
especially egregious deceptions. But no generalized Honesty Norm prevails. Thus, there is a
clear sense in which legal advocates are not, in general, committed to speaking the truth.
From the non-restrictive dialectical perspective, assertion exhibits many similarities with
the adversarial legal system. By asserting a proposition, I commit myself to advocating for it, just
as a lawyer who takes a case commits herself to advocating for her client’s position. There is no
constitutive commitment to advocate only for positions one believes, only a commitment to
advocate for whatever position one chooses. In neither case, then, does commitment to defending
the truth of what one says entrain commitment to speaking the truth in first place. Of course,
there are many disanalogies between assertion and the adversarial system: legal practice involves
explicitly codified norms directly sustained by the threat of punitive sanctions; there are
supposedly neutral adjudicators distinct from the advocates; part of practice’s rationale is the
need to preserve individual rights; and so on. But the non-restrictive dialectical approach holds
that these disanalogies conceal a more fundamental homology in normative structure.
This picture of assertion strikes many philosophers as absurd. It is admittedly a bit
extreme. So far, though, we have found no cogent argument against it.
26
§7. Intuitions of speaker-defectiveness
Philosophers often motivate the restrictive model by adducing pre-theoretic intuitions of
defectiveness. We may divide the relevant intuitions into two categories: intuitions that the
speaker is somehow blameworthy; and intuitions that, whether or not the speaker is culpable, her
assertion itself is defective.
4
I will describe these intuitions respectively as speaker-defect
intuitions and assertion-defect intuitions. A liar might elicit speaker-defect intuitions. A speaker
who asserts a false proposition she has excellent reason to believe might elicit assertion-defect
intuitions. I discuss speaker-defect intuitions in this section and assertion-defect intuitions in §8.
If we find that a speaker lied, we may blame or censure her. The restrictive model can
explain these negative reactive attitudes as registering that the speaker deliberately violated some
constitutive assertoric norm. But do the negative reactive attitudes reflect anything special about
assertion? Or do they reflect general norms that encompass both assertion and many other
actions? A useful technique here is to elicit comparative judgments regarding analogous cases of
assertoric and non-assertoric communication. Non-assertoric counterparts function somewhat
like controls in a scientific experiment.
Consider the following examples, several of which derive from two famous cases
discussed by Kant: the “murderer at the door,” and the man who packs his luggage to create the
misleading impression he is embarking on a trip.
1(a): John is helping an innocent victim evade a killer who also is John’s neighbor. The victim is
hiding in John’s car. To fool the killer, who does not know that John is harboring the victim but
who is standing far down the street, John goes to his car with a suitcase and shouts to the killer,
“I’ll be out of town for a few days,” then drives away. He does not intend to leave town.
27
1(b): Similar to 1(a), except that this time John says nothing to the neighbor. He packs a heavy
suitcase and carries it to his car. He waves to his neighbor, and he points silently to the suitcase
while loading it in the car. He does this to create the same misleading impression as in 1(a).
2(a): While preparing to drive to a marathon poker game at a nearby location, John shouts to his
nosy but harmless neighbor far down the street, “I’ll be out of town for a few days.” He lies
because he does not want his neighbor to know why he will be gone.
2(b): Stands to 2(a) as 1(b) stands to 1(a).
3(a): Iago tells Othello that Desdemona betrayed him with Cassio.
3(b): Iago shows Othello doctored photographs of Desdemona betraying him with Cassio.
5
In each pair of examples, an agent conveys roughly the same proposition. But he conveys it
assertorically in (a) and non-assertorically in (b). If the Honesty, Truth, Warrant, or Knowledge
Norm is constitutive of assertion, then (a) exhibits a specifically linguistic defect beyond
whatever defects it shares with (b). Unlike (b), (a) violates the constitutive norms of assertion.
Does the deceiver in (a) exhibit a qualitatively different type of defect than in (b)? I do
not think so. Our relevant intuitions within each pair of examples strike me as commensurate.
We view 1(a-b) as commendable, 2(a-b) as involving at most a fairly minor infraction, and 3(a-
b) as involving a serious infraction. Assertoric communication is quite different than non-
assertoric communication, so we might cite many disanalogies between each (a) scenario and the
corresponding (b) scenario. But it is hard to see how these disanalogies secure any intuitive, pre-
theoretic respect in which (a) elicits a fundamentally different censorious reaction than (b). Thus,
in explaining (a)’s blameworthiness, or lack thereof, there is no need to invoke specialized
assertoric norms. We can invoke general evaluative standards that apply both to assertion and to
28
many other actions. When assessing the deceiver for praise or blame, the fact that he employed
assertion as his mode of deception seems negligibly significant.
An imposing philosophical tradition, famously represented by Aquinas and Kant, insists
that direct lies are somehow worse than other forms of deception.
6
Bernard Williams, who
accuses Aquinas and Kant of “fetishizing assertion,” even so concedes that under certain
circumstances “there is something peculiarly odious or insulting about a lie as contrasted with
other forms of deceit” (2002, p. 118). The most popular illustration is conversational
implicature. As Augustine observed, there are many contexts in which misleading conversational
implicatures seem far less objectionable than outright lies. On this basis, Adler (1997) argues that
assertion, unlike conversational implicature, falls under a constitutive norm of truthfulness. As
another example, imagine a variant of scenario 2(b) in which John carries his luggage to his car
but pretends not to notice his neighbor observing him. This scenario, which is similar to how
Kant himself intended the luggage example, seems markedly less “odious and insulting” than a
direct lie. At the very least, such examples suggest that a lie’s defects outstrip its role in
disseminating propositions the speaker believes false. A lie is not bad simply because it deceives
or because it is intended to deceive.
Nevertheless, we should not conclude that lies are in general more deplorable than other
forms of deceit. That conclusion seems plausible only if we focus on a narrow range of
unrepresentative examples. For instance, the deceived neighbor in Kant’s version of the luggage
example does not know that John seeks to influence her beliefs. The example therefore involves
nothing resembling common knowledge of communicative intentions and expectations. Once we
incorporate this common knowledge, as in 2(b), John’s deceit becomes far more objectionable.
29
Now, John not only dupes his neighbor, he also abuses her trust. Given this abuse of trust, 2(b)
seems no less “odious and insulting” than 2(a).
Misleading conversational implicature is likewise an unrepresentative example.
Conversational implicature inherently lends itself to craftiness. It is a way of conveying
propositions without committing oneself to them. If I conversationally implicate p rather than
asserting p, it is natural for my interlocutors to wonder why. Why do I beat around the bush,
rather than just come out and say what I mean? In many contexts, then, the decision to implicate
p rather than assert p signals caveat auditor. As Adler himself observes, “the choice of a
deception rather than a lie can itself convey a message of moral effort and struggle” (1997, p.
452). Adler’s observation helps explain why misleading conversational implicatures often seem
less offensive than outright lies. Unlike the liar, a speaker who misleads through conversational
implicature provides an implicit warning, through his choice of communicative strategy, that we
should parse his message with extreme care. If his deception does not seem so bad, that is partly
because his mode of deception already broadcasts his guile.
In contrast, the modes of deception employed in scenarios 1-3(b) raise no red flags. We
may construe each scenario so that it seems quite natural for the deceiver to communicate his
message non-assertorically: in 1-2(b), because John’s neighbor is quite far away; and in 3(b),
because the photographs speak for themselves, requiring no verbal supplementation. Once
construed in this way, 2-3(b) evince intuitive defects comparable to 2-3(a). Thus, excessive focus
upon conversational implicature, at the expense of more suitable examples, encourages the
mistaken impression that assertoric deceit is peculiarly repugnant.
My goal is not to analyze why lying is wrong or how it relates to other forms of
deception. As the ethical literature on mendacity demonstrates, a complete analysis would
30
require sophisticated casuistical maneuvers applied to a wide range of cases. A good account
might invoke some of the following familiar ideas: deception often yields bad consequences for
the deceived; the deceiver abuses a bond of trust with the deceived; the deceiver acts on a maxim
that is not universalizable; the deceiver treats the deceived as a means, not as an end; the
deceiver violates our transpersonal rational interest in the pursuit of truth; the deceiver
undermines our trust in one another and thereby diminishes our ability to communicate; and so
on. My point is that, despite these complexities, we lack any antecedent reason to expect that a
good account will stigmatize assertoric deception as uniquely blameworthy when compared to
suitable varieties of non-assertoric deceit. A special pejorative stance towards assertoric
deception may be a consequence of a satisfying theory, but it is not a pre-theoretic constraint.
I turn now to cases where the speaker believes the asserted proposition but lacks
“sufficient” grounds for asserting it. Such cases often elicit the intuition that the speaker, while
not as culpable as a liar, behaves irresponsibly. The restrictive model can explain this intuition
by saying that the speaker exerts insufficient effort to obey constitutive assertoric norms.
I begin with an example made famous by Williamson. The lottery results will be
announced in a few minutes, and my friend is waiting to hear whether her ticket won. She
purchased the ticket on a lark, so she is not very invested in the outcome. I say, “Your ticket did
not win.” Call the proposition asserted “the lottery proposition.” My grounds for believing the
lottery proposition are purely probabilistic. I do not have any inside information about the
lottery. According to Williamson, I do not know the lottery proposition, even though I am
justified in believing it. Williamson also claims that “you will still be entitled to feel some
resentment when you later discover the merely probabilistic grounds for my assertion” (p. 246).
Williamson argues that we should explain this intuitive reaction through the Knowledge Norm.
31
Given the details of the lottery example, it is difficult to construct a clean non-assertoric
counterpart akin to 1-3(b). But we can study some related cases:
4(a): John’s company is planning a weekend retreat in the country. The company is about to
announce the result of a lottery, conducted last night. The lottery’s winner, if any, will be
excused from the retreat. Everyone else must attend. John is leaving for the office to learn the
lottery’s result. If his ticket won, he is determined to stay in town. If not, he is determined to go
on the retreat. He knows his ticket has very low odds of winning (let them be as low as you
please). He brings luggage with him so that he can leave directly for the retreat if necessary. As
he enters his car, he shouts to his neighbor, “I’ll be out of town for a few days.”
4(b): Similar to 4(a), except that John says nothing. Instead, he packs a heavy suitcase, waves at
his neighbor, and points silently at the suitcase while loading it into his car. He does this to
communicate that he will be out of town for a few days.
It seems fairly clear that John’s basis for believing he will leave town is probabilistic. By
Williamson’s lights, John does not know he will leave town. Suppose that, in both 4(a) and 4(b),
John’s neighbor eventually learns about the lottery and its significance. Williamson’s account
predicts that the assertoric case merits more resentment than the non-assertoric one. I think it far
from clear that pre-theoretic intuition validates this prediction. As long as John’s odds of
winning the lottery are low enough, I am not sure that 4(a) elicits any resentment at all. Even if it
does, I do not think it seems any worse than 4(b). Both cases strike us as, at worst, mildly
irresponsible but hardly grounds for strident criticism.
We can imagine a series of variants upon 4(a) and 4(b), in which we alter the nature and
strength of John’s warrant for believing that he will be out of town for a few days. In each pair of
cases, I conjecture that John elicits no more resentment in (a) than in (b).
32
Generally, the literature sparked by Williamson’s discussion has debated which
restrictive assertoric norm best explains the lottery example, not whether we should explain the
example through a restrictive norm. Weiner (2005) argues that we should explain the lottery
example through the Truth Norm and Gricean implicature, while Kvanvig (2009) favors an
account based on the Warrant Norm. Such treatments, like Williamson’s, typically cite speaker-
defect intuitions without paying even cursory attention to non-assertoric counterparts. In my
view, this is somewhat like trying to explain why property X causes cancer before checking that
subjects with X acquire cancer more frequently than subjects lacking X. Before documenting
intuitive discrepancies with comparable non-assertoric cases, we should not assume that negative
reactions elicited by assertoric performances reflect anything special about assertion.
The parity between 1-4(a) and 1-4(b) suggests that speaker-defect intuitions provide little
support for the restrictive model. Any resentment evoked by 1-4(a) reflects not specialized
assertoric norms but general norms governing belief-transmission through both linguistic and
non-linguistic means. Admittedly, I have not formulated those general norms, nor is it obvious
how to do so. But there is no evident reason why the patterns of blame and praise surrounding 1-
4(a) require a special framework of restrictive constitutive norms. On the contrary, that
framework predicts disparities that find no echo in pre-theoretic intuition.
In response to my argument, proponents of the restrictive model might propose that 1-
4(b) themselves fall under constitutive restrictive norms. On this proposal, speaker-defect
intuitions register no disparity between (a) and (b) because they both violate constitutive norms.
The challenge facing this proposal is to explain why 1-4(b) involve a practice with the
features delineated in §2: internal evaluative standards codified by constitutive norms. For
instance, in 1-2(b) and 4(b), John communicates that he will be out of town for a few days by
33
exploiting his neighbor’s mastery of folk psychology, not mastery of some pre-existing practice.
Given John’s conduct, it is common knowledge between John and his neighbor that he wants the
neighbor to notice his suitcase. The most natural explanation for why John is loading a heavy
suitcase into his car is that he is embarking on a trip that will last several days. So it is reasonable
for the neighbor to infer that John is trying to instill the belief that he is embarking on a trip that
will last several days. Since the neighbor believes from prior interactions with John that he is
honest and reliable, the neighbor concludes that John is embarking on a trip that will last several
days. This explanation does not depend in any obvious way upon constitutive norms.
§8. Intuitions of assertion-defectiveness
Assertion-defect intuitions record that the assertion itself is defective, even if the speaker
is not culpable. As Alston puts it, “the utterance is wrong, incorrect, or out of order, even if the
epistemological conditions for blameworthiness are not satisfied… [I]t was the wrong thing to
say, whatever the correct judgment as to the speaker’s fault… [T]here was something
fundamentally amiss with the utterance” (2000, p. 57, 60). The point here is not just that some
assertion is, say, false. That is something all sides can acknowledge. The point is that describing
an assertion as false constitutes a criticism of it. By asserting a falsehood, the speaker fails to
meet some relevant evaluative standard, no matter how hard she tried to reach it. As Alston puts
it, “we must distinguish the perception of an out-of-order sentence utterance from the judgment
that the assertion, or what is asserted, is false” (2000, p. 267). Similarly, one might claim that an
assertion seems ‘amiss’ if the speaker does not believe what she asserts, or does not believe it
with sufficient warrant, or does not know it. The restrictive model can explain these intuitions as
registering that the speaker, perhaps unwittingly, violated some constitutive assertoric norm.
34
A basic difficulty here is that assertion-defect intuitions are much less robust than
speaker-defect intuitions. Suppose that, mistakenly believing it is raining, I assert that it is
raining. We can all agree that my assertion is false. But is it clear that this verdict constitutes a
criticism? Do we really have a ‘perception’ that the utterance is ‘out-of-order,’ over and above
our recognition that it is false? Matters become even less clear for 1(a), in which the assertion’s
falsity and the speaker’s dishonesty might well seem the basis, not for criticism, but for
unqualified acclaim. Of course, advocates of the Truth or Honesty Norms insist that 1(a) seems
intuitively defective qua assertion, despite any countervailing moral or prudential merits. But the
putative ‘intuition’ here seems perilously close to an intuition that the restrictive model is
correct. Opponents of the restrictive model, such as Davidson, claim not to share such intuitions.
How can we decide between the restrictive and non-restrictive perspectives if we cannot
agree upon the data to be explained? Do we face a Kuhnian stalemate in which rival theorists
adduce divergent theory-laden intuitions? To some extent, perhaps. Before giving up, though, I
will examine a few representative arguments advanced by proponents of the restrictive model. I
will urge that those arguments assign assertion-defect intuitions a problematic role.
Consider the following passage from Searle (2001, p. 184):
Suppose I am not lying, but am genuinely mistaken. I sincerely said it is raining, but all
the same it is not raining. In such a case there still is something wrong with my speech
act, namely, it is false. But why is that wrong? After all, for every true proposition there
is a false one. It is wrong because the aim of a statement is to be true, and this one fails,
because it is false. When I make a statement I commit myself to its truth, and here my
mistake makes me fail in my commitment.
35
This passage moves in a tight circle between theory and data, rendering the line between premise
and conclusion difficult to discern. Apparently, Searle seeks to elicit assertoric-defect intuitions
by invoking two ideas: first, assertion involves a commitment to the truth of what one says;
second, the aim of assertion is truth. I critiqued the first idea in §6. The second idea seems too
close to the restrictive model to provide a non-circular argument for it. Setting these criticisms
aside, it seems clear that, rather than motivating the restrictive model by citing assertion-defect
intuitions, Searle motivates the intuitions by citing putative normative features of assertion. But
then Searle can hardly count the intuitions as pre-theoretic data upon which we should all agree.
Unlike Searle, Alston emphasizes that assertion-defect intuitions are elusive. His solution
is to examine first language acquisition (2000, p. 267):
We seek to get across to the small child that he is not to say “A rabbit is outside” unless
there is a rabbit outside… We try to get across to him when it is and when it is not all
right to for him to utter a certain sentence… The details of first language acquisition are
enormously complicated. But one thing that is crucially involved is the disposition on the
part of teachers to spot cases in which the learner utters a sentence in violation of an I-
rule and apply appropriate correction,
where ‘I-rule’ is Alston’s term for ‘constitutive norm of some speech act.’ Alston concludes that
ordinary practice enshrines a ‘perception’ that false assertions are ‘out-of-order,’ a perception
made manifest when we inculcate children into linguistic practice.
Alston observes that we encourage children to strive for true assertions. In fact, few
parents teach their children that false assertions are never ‘all right,’ since lies are sometimes
appropriate. Ignoring this quibble, Alston’s observation still does not support the restrictive
model. As I argued in §5, the non-restrictive dialectical perspective can explain why assertion
36
requires a pretense of sincerity. Since asserting p requires a pretense that one believes p,
asserting p is liable to induce others to believe p. Since moral norms require one, ceteris paribus,
to avoid instilling false beliefs in others, they require one, ceteribus paribus, to strive to assert
the truth. Hence, encouraging children to strive for true assertions might just be one chapter in
their moral education. So Alston’s observation does not suggest that a false assertion exhibits
any defect beyond whatever moral, epistemic, cognitive, or rational defects may have led to it.
Alston also observes that, when we discover a child has asserted a falsehood, we ‘apply
appropriate correction.’ Yet how do we apply this ‘appropriate correction’? Prototypically, we
confront the child with evidence that he asserted a false proposition and require him to concede,
at least tacitly, that he was wrong. The non-restrictive dialectical perspective can explain this
interaction as an instance of reasoned discourse, in which we try to induce the child to obey the
Retraction Norm. The fact that we expect someone to retract an assertion does not suggest that
the original assertion was defective, only that refusal to retract it would be defective.
We must distinguish two theses. The first thesis is that, when a speaker’s interlocutors
produce decisive counter-arguments against her assertion, then she must retract it. The second
thesis is that the original assertion was itself somehow defective. Our intuitions strongly support
the first thesis: if a speaker simply will not listen to reason (“That’s my story and I’m sticking to
it”) then we find her linguistic conduct highly defective. But that suggests only something like
the Retraction Norm. It does not follow that false assertions, or even assertions known by the
speaker to be false, violate some constitutive assertoric norm.
Following Searle and Alston, I have focused upon cases in which a speaker unwittingly
asserts a false proposition. What about cases where the speaker believes a true proposition but
apparently lacks ‘sufficient’ grounds for asserting it? Consider again the lottery proposition.
37
Although Williamson recognizes the distinction between intuitions of speaker- and assertion-
defectiveness (p. 261), he often blurs it, as in the following passage: “Intuitively, my grounds are
quite inadequate for that outright unqualified assertion… You will still be entitled to feel some
resentment when you later discover the merely probabilistic grounds for my assertion. I was
representing myself to you as having an authority to make the flat-out assertion which in reality I
lacked’” (p. 246). The first and third sentences of this passage strike me as ambiguous between
speaker- and assertion-defectiveness, while the second sentence evokes speaker-defectiveness.
Taken as a whole, the passage confers spurious credibility upon assertion-defect intuitions by
eliding the distinction with speaker-defect intuitions. This is no isolated expository anomaly.
Discussions of the lottery example frequently either elide the distinction or else focus exclusively
upon speaker-defect intuitions ((Weiner, 2005) illustrates the latter option).
Another worry centers again upon the crucial sentence: “You will still be entitled to feel
some resentment when you later discover the merely probabilistic grounds for my assertion.”
This sentence naturally invites us to consider an extended scenario in which I fail to defend the
lottery proposition against challenges. It therefore elicits intuitions about how I should behave
after asserting the lottery proposition, which are easily confused with intuitions about the
assertion itself. For instance, suppose friend asks, “Why do you think my ticket didn’t win?
What’s your evidence?”. I might respond by citing the low probability that the ticket won. But
my friend could retort: “I know all about the probabilities. What I want from you is an argument
that my ticket did not win, not an argument that it has a low chance of winning.” And to this I
would lack any adequate reply. I would fail to vindicate my position. Williamson regards this
failure as evidence of linguistic defectiveness. But one might instead regard the failure,
assuming it is accompanied by a refusal to retract, as itself the sole linguistic defect. It is not
38
evidence for a further transgression of ‘exceeding one’s evidential authority,’ a transgression that
already occurred with the original assertion. We must distinguish one undeniable intuition, that I
should retract my assertion when I prove unable to defend it, from a further, much more
debatable intuition that the original assertion was defective.
In general, it seems far from clear that we experience robust assertion-defect intuitions
for the lottery example, or for other examples where the speaker asserts a proposition without
‘sufficient’ grounds. We may have an intuition that the speaker behaves irresponsibly, and we
may have an intuition that the speaker must retract his assertion after failing to defend it. I argued
in the previous section that we should explain the former intuition through general moral and
social factors, not through constitutive assertoric norms. The latter intuition suggests only
something resembling the Defense or Default-Challenge Norm. I submit that we can explain any
non-controversial intuitions elicited by the lottery example, and other similar examples, through
general moral and social norms combined with non-restrictive dialectical norms.
My analysis of the lottery example is consistent with almost any epistemological
treatment. In particular, I take no stand regarding whether we know the lottery proposition or
even whether we are justified in believing it. My analysis cites only an inability to provide an
adequate argument supporting that proposition. As Alston (1989) and Audi (1993) emphasize,
the ability to produce arguments for some proposition is quite distinct from the state of being
justified in believing the proposition, let alone the state of knowing it.
Does my treatment of the lottery case presuppose that probabilistic arguments never
discharge dialectical commitments? That presupposition would be tendentious. For instance,
John might defend the assertion that he has some disease by citing the results of a blood test. The
test has an extremely slight chance of false positives, so John’s defense appears probabilistic. Yet
39
the defense will strike many as perfectly legitimate. Why might we deem probabilistic
argumentation acceptable in this scenario but not in the lottery example?
An adequate answer to this question would require a thorough analysis of probabilistic
justification, a vexed topic in contemporary epistemology.
7
Even lacking such an analysis, there
is clearly something special about the lottery scenario that sets it apart from more routine cases
like the blood test, as reflected by our unwillingness to say that one knows the lottery proposition
but not that one can know one has a disease based on a blood test. Abductive considerations may
help differentiate the two cases. The best explanation for why John’s blood test is positive is that
he has the disease; so a defense based on the blood test can appeal not just to ‘bare’ probabilities
but to abduction. Abductive considerations are irrelevant to the lottery proposition, which is a
prediction based upon good odds, not an explanation of anything.
8
Thus, one might urge that
probabilistic arguments are legitimate when they potentially admit abductive supplementation.
Whether or not this maneuver generalizes to all other intuitively acceptable probabilistic
arguments, it shows that I am not committed to any global denunciation of probabilistic
argumentation in general. My analysis assumes only that, given the specifics of the lottery
scenario, citing probabilities does not constitute an adequate defense of the lottery proposition.
Ultimately, I simply reject the putative assertion-defect intuitions that Alston, Searle, and
Williamson seek to explain. However, our discussion suggests that assertion-defect intuitions are
non-optimal candidates for pre-theoretic linguistic data. Although suggestive, they are theory-
laden and labile. They are also easily confused with other quite different intuitions. This does not
render them useless. An adequate theory of assertion must catalogue and account for them. But it
must do so with greater circumspection than proponents of the restrictive model often exercise.
40
§9. The non-restrictive dialectical perspective
Evidently, it is more difficult than one might suppose to provide a compelling argument
for the restrictive model. Although the literature contains many arguments besides those I have
discussed, I believe that my discussion casts favorable light upon the non-restrictive dialectical
perspective.
9
That perspective is much more appealing than one would suspect based on how few
contemporary philosophers advocate it. We should investigate it in more detail. At the very least,
such investigations may bring into sharper relief the strengths and weaknesses of the restrictive
model.
1
I am greatly indebted to helpful feedback from Jonathan Adler, Anthony Corsentino, Kevin Falvey, Michael
Glanzberg, Warren Goldfarb, Elizabeth Harman, Richard Heck, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Charles Parsons, and
James Pryor. I received many useful comments when I presented earlier versions of this paper at a UCSD
Philosophy Colloquium, especially from Agustín Rayo and Wayne Martin, and at the Pacific APA 2005. I am
grateful to Gary Ebbs, my commentator on the latter occasion, for his criticisms. Finally, I thank an anonymous
referee for this journal for unusually generous and helpful comments.
2
Does this approach entail that, if a speaker cannot satisfactorily defend p against a recalcitrant interlocutor, then the
speaker is not justified in believing p? No. My position concerns norms of assertion, not norms of belief. There are
no easy inferences from the former to the latter. As Alston (1989) and Audi (1993) argue, we must sharply
distinguish the ability to provide arguments for p from the state of being justified in believing p.
3
One complication is that “presenting x as y” is an opaque context. Thus, even if we agree with Williamson that
knowledge=evidence, we cannot immediately infer that one presents a proposition as evidence for other propositions
only if one represents oneself as knowing it; similarly for any putative inference from Unger’s position to (ii').
Nevertheless, it may be that the arguments offered by Unger and Williamson, when suitably modified, support
something sufficiently close to (ii').
4
Roughly speaking, speaker- versus assertion-defect intuitions correspond respectively to what DeRose (2002) calls
“secondary” versus “primary” violations of constitutive assertoric norms and what Alston (2000) calls shirking of
one’s “subjective” versus “objective” obligations.
5
(Scanlon, 1990, p. 202-3) employs an analogous argumentative strategy, vis-à-vis promising rather than asserting.
(Scanlon, 1999, p. 317-322) explains the defectiveness of lying in terms of generic moral considerations that also
apply to non-linguistic communication. See also the discussion of promising in (Cavell, 1979, p. 298).
6
For an overview of this tradition, with citations, see (MacIntyre, 1995).
7
For discussion, with citations to the literature, see (Nelkin, 2000). Nelkin argues that bare probabilistic grounds are
not sufficient for rational belief. She argues that beliefs based upon non-deductive grounds can nevertheless be
rational when those grounds incorporate some abductive element.
8
Cf. (Nelkin, 2000, p. 404-408).
9
Alston (2000, p. 78), DeRose (2002), (Williamson, 2000, p. 253), and many others argue that Moore’s paradox
supports the restrictive model. In contrast, Shoemaker (1996, p. 74-96) and Moran (2001) argue that Moore’s
paradox is fundamentally a phenomenon at the level of cognition, rather than language. The locus of deviancy lies
not with the assertions p, but I don’t know that p” or “p, but I don’t believe that p,” but with the corresponding
beliefs. As Shoemaker argues, we should first explain why there is something deviant about believing these
propositions. Once we do so, it is unlikely that we will require substantial philosophical machinery to explain why
there is something deviant about asserting them.
41
Another important observation is that one can appropriately answer any assertion by saying, “How do you
know?”. Unger deploys this observation to motivate Unger’s Thesis, and Williamson deploys it to motivate the
constitutive status of the Knowledge Norm. For critical discussion, see (Kvanvig, 2009).
Works Cited
Adler, J. 1997. Lying, deceiving, or falsely implicating. Journal of Philosophy 94, 435-452.
Alston, W. 1989. Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
---. 2000. Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Applbaum, A. 2000. Ethics for Adversaries. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Audi, R. 1993. The Structure of Justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brandom, R. 1994. Making it Explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Cavell, S. 1979. The Claim of Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
---. 2005. Truth and Predication. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
DeRose, K. 2002. Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review 111, 167-203.
Douven, I. 2006. Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility. Philosophical Review 115: 449-485.
Hamblin, C. L. 1971. Mathematical models of dialogue. Theoria 37, 130-155.
Kvanvig, J. 2009. Assertion, knowledge, and lotteries. Williamson on Knowledge, ed. D. Pritchard and P.
Greenough. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leite, A. 2005. A localist solution to the regress of justification. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83, 395-421.
MacFarlane, J. 2003. Future contingents and relative truth. The Philosophical Quarterly 53, 250-65.
---. 2005. Making sense of relative truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105, 321-39.
MacIntyre, A. 1995. Truthfulness, lies, and moral philosophers. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Volume
XVI, ed. G. B. Peterson. Salt Lake City: Utah University Press.
Moran, R. 2001. Authority and Estrangement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Nelkin, D. 2000. The lottery paradox, knowledge, and rationality. Philosophical Review 109, 373-409.
Pierce, C. S. 1934. Collected Papers, vol. V. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, J. 1955. Two concepts of rules. Philosophical Review 63, 3-32.
---. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rescorla, M. 2007. A linguistic reason for truthfulness. In Truth and Speech Acts, ed. D. Greimann and G. Siegwart.
New York: Routledge.
---. 2009a. Epistemic and dialectical regress. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87, 43-60.
---. 2009b. Shifting the Burden of Proof?. The Philosophical Quarterly 59, 86-109.
Rumfitt, I. 1995. Truth-conditions and communication. Mind 104, 827-862.
Scanlon, T. M. 1990. Promises and practices. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19, 199-226.
---. 1999. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Searle, J. 1969. Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
---. 2001. Rationality in Action. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001.
Sellars, W. 1963. Some reflections on language games. Rpt. in Sellars’s Science, Perception, and Reality. New
York: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Shoemaker, S. 1996. The First-Person Perspective and Other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thomson, J. J. 1990. The Realm of Rights. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Toulmin, S. 1958. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Unger, P. 1975. Ignorance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Watson, G. 2004. Asserting and promising. Philosophical Studies 117, 55-77.
Weiner, M. 2005. Must we know what we say? Philosophical Review 114, 227-251.
Williams, B. 2002. Truth and Truthfulness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Williamson, T. 2000. Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.